I’ve had three recent experiences and one piece of reading that have got me thinking (critically) about John Rawls’ counterfactual intuition pump. John Ralws - the American philosopher of liberal/social democracy - proposed that a good way to guide political choices is to imagine what rule on some subject or other would prevail in a society built on a collective agreement struck before anyone knew what actual life they would live in that society. Rawls asked for a choice “behind a veil of ignorance”. Think of it as agreeing the rules of a card game before the cards are dealt … (“oh! you mean low clubs are _bad_??? that’s not how I see it, now I’ve seen my hand...”)
Here
are the recent experiences that have reminded me of the habit of
thought - not an altogether positive one - that the Rawlsian question
naturally invites. The first was a very congenial supper just after the
fall of Tripoli; the second was a visit to a World War 1 war grave in
Northern France; the third was an Intelligence Squared talk given by
Stephen Pinker in which he presented his thesis on declining rates of
violence (disclosure - iQ2 employ me part time); and the reading was Elizabeth de Fontenay’s philosophical memoir (that I have used in the “quote of the day” here before).
First,
the dinner just after the fall of Tripoli. A person I like and whose
judgement I respect offered this Rawlsianism: “If I were to be tortured,
I’d rather it be at Guantanamo than in Tripoli”. It was a Rawlsianism
in the sense that the person was proposing this thought game: “all you
know is you’re going to be tortured; now come up with a preference
ranking over societies”. This was torture behind the veil of ignorance,
as it were.
Now,
I don’t really want to argue the facts. If (under duress) I really had
to make this kind of choice, I imagine I would go along with the
proposer. But the point is to try to understand why the Rawlsian
question might be a damaging one - a part of the problem, not the
solution.
In this case it seemed clear: if you use it to make these
sorts of invidious comparisons, then you tend to ignore the specificity,
the criticism and the sorts of solutions that are needed to counter two
undoubted ills. In the US, due process was easily circumvented; even a
president genuinely committed to ending the abuse could not … etc. To effectively criticise and reform, we need a real understanding of America, its politics and its culture; we don't need to know much about Libya. I am
appalled at the violence, vengefulness and blood-lust that was reported
from the victorious forces in Tripoli. I have little idea of how those
episodes of violence might be made more infrequent, but I know others
will know better. To make the comparison - to bring the two together behind a Rawlsian veil
actually disarms the right kind of criticism on all sides. A comparison
is always an invitation to ignore the specific, and the Rawlsian method
in political judgement is therefore essentially de-particularising. It might smetimes happen that we can learn what works in one context and apply to another, but that needs even more attention to the particular to avoid the possibility of creating the worst sort of well-intentioned interventions. Maybe Rawlsian comparisons are simply a bad habit for most policy decisions.
Now
for the intense experience of the particular that also now calls Rawls to mind. I was in Northern France
over half term, and we took a morning out of the delights of the coastal
holiday to visit the nearest war cemetery, which happened to be at Wimereux.
These were mostly British and Commonwealth graves from World War 1.
They commemorated those who had mostly died at a local hospital in
Boulogne-sur-Mer. A few lines of inscription on each grave, usually from
family, spoke, even in the extraordinarily reduced format, of the
specific love, place, pain, life of each. “If love could have saved, he
would not have died. His sister” … “the only son of Mr & Mrs ...” …
Thousands of testaments to loss condensed into just a few words. And
even when they were not personal stories, they were still highly
specific. A small Canadian flag had recently been planted by the
Canadian graves, and one of them was inscribed just with “One of many
Canadian Indians who gave their life for …” and here I no longer
remember what it had been claimed he had died for; the popular
placeholders were “empire”, “freedom”, “us”. The absence of the
personal, with the continued, small, official recognition in the fresh
flag, tells its own story.
The
experience in Wimereux was the antithesis of Rawlsianism - each actual
life remembered; a few words to take us away from the veil of ignorance
of the statistics of World War 1 deaths. Even the couple of seconds that
reading each inscription takes is part of a habit of mind that Rawls
wants us to avoid in political judgement.
Now
for another Rawlsian experience: Stephen Pinker’s commanding
presentation at an Intelligence Squared talk (see the video in the side-box on this page) of his impressive new book
on violence, “The Better Angels of our Nature. The decline of violence
in history and its causes”. (There is a short article by Pinker from a
couple of years ago that summarises the thesis over here.
The book is very rich analytically and Pinker is a master of
thought-provoking detail; the presentation he gave at the Royal
Geographic Society has many more of the interesting graphs than the
online article).
Pinker is utterly convincing in presenting the evidence of a reduction in rates of violence of (almost) all sorts over the last 5,000 years. (Ivan Briscoe wonders, in a powerful essay on openDemocracy, how these statistics translate into a sense of security and notes, rightly, that these are different questions). The detail is fascinating and the range of the scholarship impressive. Here is a typical example from the evidential, first part of the book.
Here is Pinker showing the "Hobbesian revolution" - from anarchic band to State and the consequent fall in rates of violent death. Again,
my point is not to go into the detail or the presentation of the
numbers - is there selection bias in the historical and archaeological
record, etc. Instead, I want to focus on the form of question that
Pinker is asking. His best evidence is on rates of death, and it is
reflected in the text with his emphasis on the thought experiment of “your risk
of reaching a violent end”. The moral thrust of Pinker’s thesis comes
from this essentially Rawlsian move: “if you had to chose which society
to be born into, and given that coming to a violent end is one of the
worst life-outcomes imaginable, where would you like to go?”
Rawls’ “A theory of justice”,
the 1971 book in which he develops his veil of ignorance argument, is
richly full of theory from many fields of social science but very short
of history and example. If he had written it in an intellectual climate
kinder to the anecdotal than was the 1960s, the book might have been
more like Pinker’s and a much better and more convincing read for it.
Rawls tries to construct a theory-based counterfactual to convince us
that we’d choose social-democratic societies in which the welfare of the
least-well off is properly regarded. Pinker offers history instead of
theory: modern, individualist, capitalist societies are pretty
convincingly the ones in which your chance of the very worst outcomes is
lowest. Just as the appreciator of fine wines might wander the aisles
of a well-stocked boutique holding Parker’s guide to score what was on
offer, so, if you were ever in a supermarket for societies, you’d do
well to carry around Pinker’s.
But
Pinker and Parker are different, of course, in an important respect:
you do choose amongst many competing wines, but you don’t choose
societies. You are born into a time and place and you engage with your
environment. How useful is Pinker’s question when it comes to that
situation? He is offering a thought experiment from decision theory:
“which society would you choose? which is least risky?” Yet, as Pinker
himself argues (approvingly citing utilitarian philosopher Peter
Singer), one of the important driving forces for the reduction in the
riskiness of society are the habits of empathy. Human empathy asks not
“what would you choose?”, but rather “what is it like to be you rather than me?”
So
here is the issue: does Pinker’s central question, the one of risk,
itself contribute to reducing the very worst risks? or is some other
habit of thought involved? Since we’re not in the social supermarket,
what habits of mind, what thought experiments, prepare us properly for
social choice? My moment at the Wimereux war grave suggests a different
mental exercise. What if, instead of the imaginary social supermarket,
you decided to spend an imaginary 20 seconds in front of every violent
death, a virtual war cemetery? I doubt you would ever in a lifetime
leave the 20th century and its mass produced industrialised violence.
Instead of plotting the rate of death, why not plot the acreage of
imaginary war graves? That graph would point decidedly and depressingly
upwards, not downwards.
I
had the good fortune to be able to put the point to Stephen Pinker, and
his reply was two-fold. The first was a recommendation to read to the
end of the book where he explicitly makes this point. And so he does:;
this is taken from his penultimate paragraph:
“...I have adopted a voice that is analytic, and at times irreverent, because I believe the topic has inspired too much piety and not enough understanding. But at no point have I been unaware of the reality behind the numbers. To review the history of violence is to be repeatedly astounded by the cruelty and waste of it all, and at times to be overcome with anger, disgust and immeasurable sadness. I know that behind the graphs there is a young man who feels a stab of pain and watches the life drain slowly out of him …. [and] the numbers are not in the hundreds, or the thousands, or even the millions, but in the hundreds of millions - an order of magnitude that the mind staggers to comprehend, with deepening horror as it comes to realize just how much suffering has been inflicted by the naked ape upon its own kind.”
The second part of his answer was that modernity would certainly cover more space in the virtual cemetery, but that it has also allowed vastly more fulfilled lives than other periods. This, in a sense, is his way back to the Rawlsian veil of ignorance. If you are in that position of choice, you care about the likelihood of good lives as well as the extent of terrible ends.
This Rawlsian attitude is sometimes right. Policy does need to be made, and impersonality is important in many of the operations of the State and the law. But we shouldn’t think it is obviously the right attitude for us in our contemplation of history. Here, finally, is the connection to Elisabeth de Fontenay’s philosophical memoir, “Actes de Naissance”. She writes:
“I do not accept that conflicts are resolved through some
dialectical achievement of synthesis … Isn’t there a huge degree of bad
faith - or even callousness - in accepting the divisions [of conflict]?
‘Every determination is a negation’ according to Spinoza … Thus, [in
the face of conflict] I remain in two minds, and I don’t think this is
duplicity. I have never sacrificed anything for anything else, and
perhaps that is why I have never held or seized anything...”
Rawlsianism,
and utilitarianism more generally, tries to always put us in the stance
of the decision - to resolve the conflict of goods and bads - of
realised lives versus violent deaths - by netting them out, de
Fontenay’s “dialectical achievement of synthesis”. Instead, she proposes
a stance that avoids the negation - in this case the denial of the
reality of the massive scale of violent death that becomes drowned in
the synthesis represented by rates of death. When de Fontenay says that her two-mindedness has led her to "never holding and seizing" anything, she may be describing some philosophical detachment; but the military metaphor is very striking in the context.Pinker’s statistics and his
analysis of modernity tell an important story. But it is important not to forget his penultimate paragraph. Remain in two minds but without
duplicity. Avoid the bad faith of utilitarian netting out. What good,
after all, does it do?
Read more
Get our weekly email
Comments
We encourage anyone to comment, please consult the oD commenting guidelines if you have any questions.